Differentiating Between Concrete and Transcendental Worlds: The School of Names and Neo-Daoism

The distinction between name (ming) and substance (shi) is usually something Chinese philosophers did not touch upon because it was a metaphysical discussion--it meant that names had a life of their own apart from their substance.  During the Warring States period, the art of debate reached a height in China, as there seemed to be ample opportunities for private tutors in debates and arguments.  What was similar to the Greek sophists developed in China, who specialized in winning a debate irrespective of moral rules.  It was during this period of time that metaphysics developed in China, although it was not in a position to rival Confucian learning that developed into mainstream culture.  The discussion of the School of Names (so called because they recognized names--concepts, and contents as two separate things) is partly a result of the contrast between Chinese philosophy (largely ethical) and Western philosophy (largely logical) that many Chinese scholars made in the 20th century.  It is their way of weighing Chinese philosophy against Western philosophical standards.  The very fact that Fung Yu-lan, a prominent 20th century Chinese philosopher, elaborated on the School of Names and its connection with the neo-Daoists, neither of which received much attention in Chinese historical writings, was because of his search for a more cognitive tradition (in contrast to an ethical one) in Chinese philosophy.  In doing so, Fung restored some importance to the School of Names and the neo-Daoists that they always deserved but never quite got in Chinese history because they were at variance with Confucian thinking. 

The initial Chinese sophists during the Warring States Era were lawyers and focused on what twists and turns they could make of names.    There were two trends in the School of Names: one, to emphasize the changeable and relative nature of actual things, and the other, the intension (meaning all the possible things a word could describe) of names and word tricks based on the meaning of words. 

Representatives of the School of Names:

Hui Shi (350-260 B.C.): from the state of Song/Sung, was an expert on making twists and turns with names and taking advantage of the relative nature of concrete things.  His writings were recorded in Zhuang Zi/Chuang Tzu's "The World."  Using stories such as the Yellow River (Fung, 84) to illustrate the relativity between big and small things in the world, Fung goes on to contrast comparisons between concrete things (such as the sizes of the Yellow River and the sea), and the unstable nature of those comparisons, in contrast to the names, which are permanent and unchanging , such as the definitions of great, and small. (Fung, 85)  Everything is relative, therefore everything can be different, or similar, depending on what criteria one uses toward the comparison. 

Kung-sun Lung: (284-259 B.C.) Kung-sun (this was his last name, one of a handful Chinese last names that have two syllables and two characters; the majority of Chinese last names are single character ones) was famous for his statement: a white horse is not a horse.  Kung-sun made his argument by focusing on the internal nature of words, such as "horse," and "white." 

Because in the Chinese language there are no inflections (no affixes to words), nor articles (the), a word such as horse has to stand in for both actual horses and a universal concept of horse.  Kung-sun Lung refers to them as pointers, meaning they have to designate something abstract and universal.

This separation between name and content contributed to a transcendental nature of Dao/Tao to Daoism/Taoism.  This transcendence was the contribution of the School of Names and the writings of people such as Kung-sun Lung.  It also led to a Daoist reinterpretation of Confucius

Reinterpreting Confucius with Daoist Transcendence. 

600-700 years after Confucius, in the Han Dynasty (206 B.C.-220 A.D.), there was a revival of Daoism, but this round, Confucius was more venerated than Lao Zi by the neo-Daoists.  Only, Confucius was interpreted along Daoist lines.  The Daoist advocacy of do-nothing was applied to Confucius.  Since the world admired by the Daoists was the primordial, non-differentiated, "empty" world (here, empty refers to an un-differentiation of objects in the world, not that the world was really empty), the highest virtue for the neo-Daoists was for a sage to attain the stage of emptiness, and what was more, forget about this emptiness (indicating the distinction between the sage and the undifferentiated world was erased so the sage was no longer conscious of any difference between himself and the empty world)  Confucius only talked about being, and not non-being, because, to these Daoists, Confucius forgot that his mind, and the world, were empty, and he could not use non-being as a subject of instruction. (Fung, 219)   

Dao/Tao is "nothing"

Two neo-Daoists stood out in their new explanation of "nothingness" and Dao in the Three Kingdoms Era (220-265 A.D.), a period of time when three kingdoms coexisted after the disintegration of the Han Dynasty, and the ensuing Jin/Chin Dynasty (265-420 A.D.) when the Kingdom of Wei conquered the other two kingdoms and reunified China.  Hsiang Hsiu (Xiang Xiu) (221-300) and Kuo Hsiang/Guo Xiang (d.312 A.D.) further elaborated on the idea of Dao to mean nothing apart from the natural movements/changes of everything in the universe.  When Lao Zi and other Daoists talked about non-being, they meant an undifferentiated universe.  Hsiang Hsiu and Kuo Hsiang (Fung simplified them into Hsiang-Kuo)  said there was no separate Dao governing an undifferentiated universe, and thus Dao was really nothing, meaning non-existence.  The universe spontaneously changed following no particular Dao.

n. Partly lighted shadow on the skirts of a total
shadow. ~al a. [L paene almost, umbra shade]

Hsiang-Kuo's argument

Hsiang and Kuo were against the traditional arguments that traced the myriad things in the universe to one original source: Just as penumbra was produced by shadow, shadow by bodily form, and form by creator.  Instead, they argued that everything was self-producing.  (Fung, 221)  And there was no separate Dao or rules governing the creation of everything in the universe.  Everything depends on other things in the universe to exist: when certain conditions exist, certain things are produced.  But things are not caused by one particular thing in the universe.  (Fung, 222)

Implications of Hsiang-Kuo's arguments

Conclusion:

Hsiang Hsiu and Kuo Hsiang developed a transcendental approach to knowledge, values, and all phenomena in the world.  Their high relativism cultivated a highly irreverent/anti-establishment (to borrow a modern term) attitude that defied a singular approach to truth and any attempt at establishing orthodoxy.  The transcendental dimension they added to Daoism facilitated the introduction of Buddhism into China, something we will discuss in later sessions.